Qualia: An Exploration of Subjective Experience

Inspired by a fascinating conversation with Jim over coffee, I continued to explore the topic of qualia with Gemini. The following paper is the result of our collaboration.

---

Qualia: An Exploration of Subjective Experience

Lonnie Mandigo and Gemini, October 2025

Abstract


This paper explores the philosophical concept of qualia—the subjective, qualitative character of conscious experience. It frames the central debate through the analogy of a map versus the territory it represents: are qualia an emergent, functional representation of complex neural processes (the map), or an irreducible, intrinsic property of those processes (the territory)? This tension is examined through the lens of the "Mary's Room" thought experiment. The paper further provides a functional analysis of the roles qualia play both within a single mind (intra-subjective operations) and in mediating our understanding of other minds (inter-subjective operations). We conclude that the debate hinges on the nature of the "explanatory gap," questioning whether it represents a fundamental limit of physicalism or a cognitive illusion rooted in the inherent imprecision of all mental abstractions.

1. Introduction: The Nature of the Problem

At the heart of the mind-body problem lies the phenomenon of qualia: the raw, first-person "what-it's-like-ness" of an experience. It is the taste of chocolate, the feeling of warmth, or the visual experience of the color red. While neuroscience can describe the physical correlates of these events—the chemical reactions on the tongue or the neural firing in the visual cortex—a descriptive gap remains. The "Hard Problem of Consciousness" is not about how the brain processes information, but why that processing should be accompanied by any subjective feeling at all. This paper examines the nature of this gap and the arguments that seek to define or dissolve it.

2. The Core Tension: Is Experience a Map or the Territory?

A useful analogy to frame the debate is that of a map and the territory it represents.

  • The Territory is the physical reality of the brain: a complex, dynamic system of neural and chemical interactions.

  • The Map is the quale: the brain's simplified, high-level, and functional representation of its own state.

This distinction gives rise to two primary philosophical positions:

  1. The Physicalist View (The Quale is the Map): This position holds that qualia are nothing more than the brain's internal representations. Proponents argue that to seek a further, "mysterious" substance for the feeling itself is to fundamentally misunderstand the nature of representation. The map is not made of "magic paper"; its representative function is its reality.

  2. The Anti-Physicalist View (The Quale is a Property of the Territory): This position contends that qualia are a real, intrinsic property generated by the physical territory. This property—a "glow" of subjective awareness—is only accessible from a first-person perspective and is therefore not reducible to a third-person description of the territory's functions.

3. A Case Study: The Mary's Room Thought Experiment

Frank Jackson's "Mary's Room" thought experiment is designed to test these competing intuitions. It posits a brilliant neuroscientist, Mary, who knows every physical fact about color vision but has never seen color herself. The question is, upon seeing a red rose for the first time, does she learn something new?

  • If she does learn something new (the fact of what it is like to see red), it suggests that there are non-physical facts, and the anti-physicalist view holds.

  • If she does not learn a new fact, but merely gains a new ability (the ability to recognize red by sight), then physicalism remains intact. The debate thus shifts to whether the "what-it's-like-ness" is a form of knowledge (a fact) or a form of skill (an ability).

4. A Functional Analysis of Qualia

Regardless of their ultimate nature, qualia serve distinct operational roles within a cognitive system. These intra-subjective operations demonstrate the functional utility of consciousness as an abstraction mechanism for a complex system. Key operations include: Comparison and Discrimination (judging one apple as sweeter than another), Memory and Imagination (recalling the feeling of a past event), Association and Integration (linking the smell of bread to a feeling of comfort), Attention and Modulation (focusing on a single voice in a crowd), and Valuation and Affect (assigning pleasure or displeasure to a sensation, which in turn motivates behavior).

5. The Problem of Other Minds: Inter-Subjective Operations

The private nature of qualia necessitates a set of indirect operations to bridge the gap between minds. These operations are predicated on the assumption that other entities possess an inner world. They include: Inference and Simulation (modeling another's mind), Communication and Translation (encoding experience into symbols), Empathy and Affective Resonance (feeling with another), and Shared Attention (creating a common focus). The very nature of these operations changes depending on whether we believe the other entity has qualia (a person) or is a pure mechanism (a thermostat). This is not an arbitrary distinction but a pragmatic cognitive shift. Faced with a limited processing capacity, the brain employs different abstraction models for different systems. For a simple mechanism, a mechanical model is efficient. For a complex social agent, predicting behavior from a purely mechanical level is computationally far more challenging. Instead, the brain deploys a far more sophisticated abstraction: the qualia or 'intentional' model. By assuming the other entity has beliefs, desires, and subjective experiences, we can make powerful and efficient predictions about their behavior. From this meta-perspective, the qualia model and the mechanical model are both cognitive tools—different maps for different territories—used to render a complex world understandable.

6. Conclusion: The Explanatory Gap as an Abstraction Artifact

The exploration of qualia reveals a fundamental tension in our understanding of the world. A consistent physicalist view holds that consciousness is an elegant abstraction—a "user interface" for a complex biological machine. From this perspective, the "explanatory gap" is not a feature of reality, but a cognitive illusion.

This illusion can be understood through the nature of abstraction itself. Any abstraction mechanism, by definition, introduces imprecision and inaccuracy; the only perfect model of the universe is the universe itself, and all other models require a loss of information. The qualia model is mysterious because we are, on some level, aware of the information that has been lost in the abstraction from the full complexity of the brain. To satisfy our innate desire for completeness and internal consistency, we replace that informational gap with mystical factors. The "hard problem," from this viewpoint, is the name we give to our discomfort with an incomplete map.

The opposing view maintains that the first-person, subjective nature of qualia represents a genuinely distinct phenomenon that cannot be fully captured by any third-person, functional description. The ultimate resolution, therefore, may not come from discovering a new fact about the world, but from understanding why the very architecture of our abstractive consciousness makes the question so profoundly challenging in the first place.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Is Humanity Worth Saving?

Understanding

Identity